1
Exploring the Interface Between the Common Law of Tort and Statute Law
Annual Richard Davies Lecture
For the Personal Injuries Bar Association
29 November 2023
Philip Sales
*
I am grateful for the invitation from the Association to deliver the annual Richard Davies lecture.
Twenty years ago Professor Jack Beatson attacked what he termed the “oil and water” approach
to the relationship between common law and statute, which sees them as separate sources of law
which do not intermingle. But as he said: “Why should statutory manifestations of principle [...]
not be part of the armoury of the common law judge in determining a hard case and seeking to
determine what best fits the fundamental principles of the legal system?”
2
My lecture pursues Jack Beatson’s theme in the context of the law of tort. I want to explore how
the existence and scope of a duty of care in common law is informed by statute. This includes
examining how duty of care analysis may be bound up with considerations of public policy. Public
policy is a contested field. Where can judges look for guidance on public policy to legitimise the
way in which it is prayed in aid by the courts in their reasoning? Statutes are an important source
of guidance on public policy and so are capable of informing the courts’ approach to duty of care
questions at common law.
I will begin by examining the historical foundations of the concept of the duty of care, as that will
help to frame the analysis which follows.
1. Historical foundations of the concept of the duty of care
It was only following the emergence of an independent action for negligence that duty of care
began to play an analytical role in the determination of questions of liability.
3
At around the same
time, contract and tort were emerging as distinct legal entities. Generally, this distinction was
unproblematic, as actions based on non-performance of an undertaking were clearly contractual,
and actions based on the negligent causation of harm independent of any prior relationship were
clearly in tort.
By the start of the 19
th
century, however, procedural differences between contract and tort were
emerging. To avoid the procedural disadvantages associated with contract, plaintiffs who had
suffered an injury in the course of the negligent mis-performance of a contract began to formulate
their declarations in tort by focusing on the source of the defendant’s duty. In Boorman v Brown,
4
for
*
Lord Sales, Justice of the Supreme Court of the United Kingdom. I am grateful to my judicial assistant, Alex Hughes,
for his excellent assistance in preparing this lecture.
2
Jack Beatson, “The Role of Statute in the Development of Common Law Doctrine” (2001) 117 LQR 247, 252.
3
See James Plunkett, The Duty of Care in Negligence (2018, Hart Studies in Private Law), chapter 2.
4
(1842) 3 QB 511.
2
example, the Court of Exchequer held that a broker owed a duty to his client because “the principle
[…] would seem to be that the contract creates a duty, and the neglect to perform that duty, or the
nonfeasance, is a ground of action upon a tort.
5
In this sense, then, duty was being employed as
a way of expanding the scope of the tort of negligence, by reformulating breaches of contractual
duties, which arose by reason of agreement, as breaches of duties in tort, which in other cases
arose by reason of law.
In parallel with this interaction between contract and tort, an interaction was emerging between
tort and statute in analysing the duty requirement. In Parnaby v Lancaster Canal,
6
for example, a
statute required the defendant canal company to maintain clear passage on the canal, and to that
end gave it powers to dredge up and remove sunken vessels. A sunken vessel was not removed,
with the result that the claimant’s boat using the canal was damaged. The claimant sued the canal
company in tort. The defendant company argued that the statute, which imposed a penalty when
a boat obstructed the canal and empowered the canal owners to remove it, was “permissive, not
imperative”.
7
Tindal CJ accepted that the statute did not impose a duty on the company but went
on to hold that a duty existed at common law, “not perhaps to repair the canal, or absolutely free
it from obstructions, but to take reasonable care, so long as they keep it open for the public use of
all who may choose to navigate it, that they may navigate without danger to their lives or
property.”
8
In the second half of the 19
th
century, as the action of negligence expanded, judges began to insist
that a duty of care was a necessary ingredient. The focus of the duty analysis changed from being
used to expand the scope of the action to playing an exclusionary role. One of the earliest such
cases was Degg v Midland Railway Company,
9
where Bramwell B held: “There is no absolute or
intrinsic negligence; it is always relative to some circumstances of time, place, or person … there
can be no action except in respect of a duty infringed.
10
At the same time, considerations of policy
also started to emerge more overtly in judicial decisions. Courts were quick to deny the existence
of a duty where they felt it would lead to a significant extension in liability. In Morgan v The Vale of
Neath Railway Co,
11
for example, Pollock CB denied that a master owed a duty to a servant who
had been injured by the negligence of another servant because: “It appears to me that we should
be letting in a flood of litigation, were we to decide the present case in favour of the plaintiff.
12
Lord Atkin’s speech in Donoghue v Stevenson sought to produce a unified analytical approach to the
tort of negligence based on the duty of care concept. It built on the attempt by Sir William Brett
MR in 1883 in Heaven v Pender
13
to do the same. Lord Atkin’s neighbour principle was based on the
idea of foreseeability and a rather slippery limiting notion of “proximity”.
14
There was resistance
to making duty of care a governing concept, including by Buckland who said it was an “unnecessary
fifth wheel on the coach”.
15
However, it has remained central, essentially for two reasons. First, it
provides an important yet flexible focus for attention on the precise nature of the relationship
5
Ibid., 526 (Tindal CJ).
6
(1839) 11 AD & E 223; 113 ER 400.
7
Ibid., 403.
8
Ibid., 407-8.
9
(1857) 1 H&N 773.
10
Ibid., 78182.
11
(1865) 1 QB 149 (Ex).
12
Ibid., 155.
13
(1883) 11 QB 503, 509.
14
Donoghue v Stevenson [1932] AC 562, 580–81.
15
W Buckland, “The Duty to Take Care” (1935) 51 LQR 637.
3
between the parties and the normative implications of that in a range of contexts. Secondly, it
provides a useful basis for striking out claims at an early stage, if analysis shows no duty of care is
owed, thereby obviating the expense and delay associated with a full trial on the facts.
The modern formulation to determine the existence of the duty of care arrived with the decision
in Caparo v Dickman.
16
Lord Bridge observed that what emerges from the caselaw is that, “in
addition to the foreseeability of damage, necessary ingredients in any situation giving rise to a duty
of care are that there should exist between the party owing the duty and the party to whom it is
owed a relationship characterised by the law as one of ‘proximity’ or neighbourhood’ and that the
situation should be one in which the court considers it fair, just and reasonable that the law should
impose a duty of a given scope upon the one party for the benefit of the other.”
17
Where a duty of care is authoritatively established in the caselaw, there is no warrant for constantly
revisiting its existence by repeated application of the “fair, just and reasonable" formula.
18
But
where there is an open question whether a duty of care exists in a particular context, resort to that
formula is appropriate.
2. Considerations of policy in the duty of care analysis
The third stage of the Caparo test, whether it is fair, just, and reasonable to impose a duty, invites
attention to considerations of policy.
19
This is inevitable, because when a court declares that a
common law duty of care exists, the state imposes legal obligations on a person. The court
performs a role which is to some degree legislative. That is so even if the process is conceived of
as a sort of recognition of something identified through the application of background legal
principles. Those background principles themselves involve resort to policy considerations. For
this purpose “policy” must be identified in a reasonably determinate way, and in a manner which
properly legitimises the court’s decision to impose the duty.
20
For example, in Hedley Byrne v Heller Lord Pearce said that the “sphere of the duty of care in
negligence […] depends ultimately upon the courts’ assessment of the demands of society for
protection from the carelessness of others”.
21
Lord Denning referred to this in the Court of Appeal
in Home Office v Dorset Yacht and said that the determination of a duty of care was at bottom a
matter of public policy which we, as judges, must resolve”,
22
a comment that was later approved
by Lord Diplock in the House of Lords.
23
Policy considerations are perceived to play an important
part in determining questions regarding duty of care, particularly at the ultimate appellate level.
24
How, then, can the courts formulate a concrete guide to the policy considerations in recognising
or denying a duty of care at common law, or extending or narrowing the scope of such a duty?
16
[1990] 2 AC 605.
17
Ibid., 617-8.
18
Robinson v Chief Constable of West Yorkshire Police [2018] UKSC 4, [27].
19
Michael v Chief Constable of South Wales Police [2015] AC 1732, [160] (Lord Kerr). See also Customs and Excise
Commissioners v Barclays Bank [2007] 1 AC 181, 190 (Lord Bingham).
20
Cf Stephen Guest, Ronald Dworkin (2013, 3
rd
ed, Stanford University Press), 91: policy may be a term which is “used
loosely, sometimes even just to mean that the judge has run out of good arguments.”
21
Hedley Byrne v Heller [1964] AC 465, 536.
22
[1969] 2 QB 412, 426.
23
[1970] AC 1004, 1058.
24
J. Morgan, “‘Policy Reasoning in Tort Law’: The Courts, the Law Commission and the Critics” (2009) 125 LQR 215,
215. For a further example of explicit policy reasoning, see the speech of Lord Wilberforce in the “nervous shock”
case, McLaughlin v O’Brian [1983] 1 AC 410, 421-422.
4
Looking to statutes can play a significant role for the courts in approaching this question. Statutes
are a concrete expression of the public interest in legal form, endorsed by the democratic
legislature. Moreover, law in the form of statutes increasingly governs in many contexts and it is
unavoidable that the courts, in exercising their quasi-legislative role to impose duties of care, have
to take account of this. A common law duty of care has to slot in alongside, and be coherent with,
any relevant statutory regime in the field of its application. In Guido Calabresi’s words, the
common law has to be a common law for the age of statutes.
25
3. Explicit reliance on public policy by reference to statute
In conducting the duty analysis, the common law must always give way to statute and any statutory
duty must be complied with. It therefore often makes sense to address the question of explicit
statutory rules at the outset, because statute may impose, or preclude, a duty of care.
26
In some cases, a statute might be found to impose a duty itself, breach of which sounds in damages
at common law. In a sense, these are simple and relatively uninteresting cases, in that statute itself
tells us the answer. In these cases, public policy is fully incorporated in the statute itself. But this
itself calls for some process of policy analysis to determine the purpose which the statute was
intended to serve.
In other cases, however, there is a more subtle interplay between statute and common law. These
are cases in which a common law rule is framed by reference to, or in the light of, public policy,
and draws on statute to inform the content of the public policy standard to be applied. The way
in which this happens is a general phenomenon, of which duty of care analysis is one part.
Leaving tort to one side for a moment, one can see this phenomenon in contract law. Public policy
may render a contract unenforceable. Changes in legislation have operated as a “catalyst” to
prompt changes in judge-made law.
27
An example is the law in relation to champerty and
maintenance, the doctrine which rendered unenforceable contracts to provide funding to promote
litigation.
28
The policy was the desire to ensure that individuals did not stir up litigation at no risk
to themselves.
29
But such a view began to be called into question. Legal rights ought to be capable
of enforcement, but litigation is expensive. Third party funding may be a necessary part of giving
the rule of law practical effect. The introduction of legal aid in 1949
30
effected an important
statutory exception to the rule against maintenance. Conditional fee agreements were introduced
by the Courts and Legal Services Act 1990.
This affected the courtsperception of the public interest. In 2002 the Court of Appeal in Factortame
(No 8) explained that only those funding arrangements that tended to “undermine the ends of
justice” should fall foul of the prohibition on maintenance and champerty.
31
This opened the way
to more extensive third party funding of legal claims as a means to secure access to justice.
25
G. Calabresi, A Common Law for the Age of the Statutes (Harvard University Press, 1982).
26
See Gorringe v Calderdale Metropolitan Borough Council [2004] UKHL 15, [3] (Lord Steyn).
27
M. Leeming, “Theories and Principles Underlying the Development of the Common Law(2013) UNSW Law
Journal 36(3) 1001, 1002.
28
Law Commission, Proposals for the reform of the Law Relating to Maintenance and Champerty (1966), para 9; Hill v Archbold
[1968] 1 QB 686.
29
Wallis v Duke of Portland (1798) 3 Ves. Jun. 494, 502.
30
The Legal Aid and Advice Act 1949.
31
R (Factortame) v Secretary of State for Transport (No 8) [2003] QB 381, 400.
5
4. The implicit operation of public policy in duty of care analysis by reference to statute
In relation to duty of care, there are many cases where the statute confers rights or imposes
obligations but is silent on the extent to which a common law duty of care may exist alongside
them. In this category of case public policy operates implicitly, with the judicial analysis latching
onto the statutory duties to inform policy arguments in shaping common law duties.
Many judicial statements in recent tort cases make reference to the need to be “principled” in
developing the law,
32
with principle operating in contrast to “policy”. Certain judges have sought
to explain that the type of policy that is relevant to the determination of whether the defendant
owes a duty of care is primarily “legal” policy. The aim is perhaps to indicate that this type of policy
lies within the competence of judges.
Under Caparo, the three elements can be seen as a balance between questions of principle and
policy. The principles of “foreseeability” and proximity” must be considered against the more
policy-driven question of whether it is “fair, just and reasonable” to impose a duty of care; but the
other two elements have a policy dimension as well. Consideration of policy in this analysis is part
of the positive process of establishing a duty of care, rather than a merely limiting factor. The
Supreme Court clarified in the Robinson case that Caparo should be seen as applying only to novel
categories of case.
33
Within an “established duty category”, there is no need to discuss the notions
of proximity, or of what is “fair, just and reasonable”. This is because Caparo only assists with the
consideration of extensions to established duty situations. The key contribution of Caparo was
described by the Supreme Court in the Poole Borough Council case as its emphasis on incremental
development.
34
Courts should determine cases on the basis of established principle, thus placing
cases within legal categories. Pragmatism, and policy, are not directly referred to as decisive.
But this leaves something of a gap: how can future courts decide when to allow incremental
development? Policy factors have to inform the determination of whether and how far to extend
a duty of care incrementally. To say that development should be incremental only tells one that
that dramatic leaps of development are ruled out. This is justified on grounds of the need to ensure
a reasonable degree of predictability in the law and by the limited role of courts to effect change
in the law without the democratic mandate of legislation. But it does not in itself tell one whether
the law ought to be developed, or in what direction. Perhaps a proposed and admittedly
incremental development is not in fact justified. How can one tell if that is so or not?
Since consideration of policy is inevitable and since statute encapsulates public policy with a
democratic imprimatur, looking at statutory duties may be an essential part of the analysis.
From the perspective of the law of tort, statutory duties can be divided into two types. The first is
duties which are clear, precise, designed to benefit a particular group including the claimant, and
intended to be actionable at common law.
35
Such duties are actionable through the distinct tort of
breach of statutory duty. One needs to look at the object of the statutory duty in question. As
explained in Cutler v Wandsworth Stadium: “if a statutory duty is prescribed but no remedy by way
of penalty or otherwise for its breach is imposed, it can be assumed that a right of civil action
accrues to the person who is damnified by the breach. For, if it were not so, the statute would be
32
See, e.g., Fairchild v Glenhaven Funeral Services [2003] 1 AC 32, [36] (Lord Nicholls).
33
Robinson (n 18), [27].
34
GN v Poole Borough Council [2019] UKSC 25, [64].
35
X (Minors) v Bedfordshire County Council [1995] 2 AC 633, 731
6
but a pious aspiration. But ‘where an Act […] creates an obligation, and enforces the performance
in a specified manner, we take it to be a general rule that performance cannot be enforced in any
other manner’.”
36
However, this general rule is subject to exceptions, which are policy-based. In Black v Fife Coal Co,
affirmed in Cutler, Lord Kinnear considered, in relation to a statutory duty on an employer to take
actions to protect employees, that there was no basis “for maintaining that a proceeding by way of
penalty is the only remedy allowed by the statute”.
37
This was determined by looking at the purpose
(that is, the underlying policy) of the statute to determine for whose benefit it was intended and
what could be inferred from that to be the intended remedial consequence. That statute was
intended to ensure the safety of the employees so it was held that there was a corresponding cause
of action in damages at common law for the employees where there was a breach of the duty.
38
This can be contrasted with the facts in Cutler, where the primary intention of the statute was to
regulate the conduct of racetracks, not to benefit bookmakers, even if “in consequence of those
regulations being observed some bookmakers [carrying on business there] will be benefited”.
39
The second, more usual, type of statutory duty is one which is not actionable at common law. A
very general statutory duty, or one not designed to benefit a particular group of people including
the claimant, or one that Parliament did not intend to be actionable in damages, will not be
enforceable through the action for breach of statutory duty.
40
Many duties where there is a criminal
or other sanction set out in the statute will fall into this category, although this may not be
conclusive. An example of a duty not actionable at common law arose in O’Rourke v Camden.
41
The
duty to offer accommodation to those who are homeless was not narrow and defined and was not
for the benefit of a prescribed class of people. It was a general social welfare duty. A person who
was not housed when he presented himself as homeless could not seek damages in tort, and must
instead seek judicial review.
42
Statutory duties may be contrasted with statutory powers which confer discretion: these specify
that the conferee of the power may do something, not that they must. Public law provides
remedies if discretion is improperly exercised, or if there is an improper failure to exercise a power.
Generally speaking, in light of the Cutler type of analysis, damages are not available in an action for
breach of public law in relation to the exercise of discretion. However, in certain situations the
general criteria under common law to identify a duty of care may be satisfied when a public
authority acts in exercise of a public law discretion, so that a common law cause of action arises.
This is an interesting and difficult area to which I will return.
At this stage, I want to highlight the extent to which statutory duties can be relevant to the common
law duty of care analysis between private persons. The existence of legislation might be taken as a
pointer of particular weight regarding the public interest, and of the direction in which the
common law should be developed. One could say that in these instances the statute operates as a
36
Cutler v Wandsworth Stadium Ltd [1949] AC 398, 407 (Lord Simonds).
37
Black v. Fife Coal Co Ltd [1912] AC 149, 165.
38
Ibid.
39
Cutler (n 36), 409.
40
Phillips v Britannia Hygienic Laundry Co Ltd [1923] 2 KB 832, 840 (Bankes LJ).
41
[1998] AC 188.
42
Ibid., 193.
7
positive social proposition, capable of drawing the common law along in the same direction of
travel.
43
For example, Reynolds v Times Newspapers
44
concerned the scope of defences available to a
newspaper which publishes an article which is defamatory of a politician. There was an established,
but narrow, defence of qualified privilege for a person who is under a duty to report on the conduct
of another, so that no liability would attach if they did so in good faith and without malice. The
defendant argued for adoption of a wider version of that defence to cover a newspaper which
reports honestly on the conduct of a leading politician, on the grounds that it is under a form of
moral obligation to report to the public on what it believes to be the truth. The House of Lords
was conscious that Parliament had passed the Human Rights Act 1998 (“HRA”) which effectively
incorporated a similar wide view of protections for fair journalism by newspapers drawn from the
case law of the Strasbourg court in relation to article 10 of the European Convention on Humant
Rights (freedom of expression), even though the Act had not yet come into force. The House took
this as one indication, among others, that it would be right for it to extend the defence of qualified
privilege at common law. The legislation showed the direction of travel of public policy, in a way
which supported and could not be taken as blocking the development of the common law.
45
Looking further back in time, one sees the interface between the common law and statute in the
area of the employer/employee relationship.
46
Historically, the primary structural feature of
employers’ liability for injuries suffered by their workmen was the doctrine of common
employment, which provided that an employer was not liable for an injury to one of his employees
where it was caused by a fellow employee’s carelessness in the course of common work with the
injured employee. The theory was that an employee had assumed the risk of carelessness of fellow
employees by agreeing to work alongside them. Exceptions to the doctrine came to be recognised,
such as the tort of breach of statutory duty. In Groves v Lord Wimborne, the Court of Appeal held
that the defence of common employment was unavailable where a worker had been injured by
machinery that, in breach of the employer’s statutory duty, had not been securely fenced.
47
The
statutory obligation was placed upon the employer personally, which allowed the courts to say that
a breach of it fell outside the doctrine of common employment because the doctrine was all about
the risk that a third party might breach their duty. Here, by contrast, the employer was being made
accountable for a breach of his own duty.
48
It was not until 1937, with the decision of the House of Lords in Wilsons and Clyde Coal Company v
English,
49
that the modern duty of care owed by an employer to an employee was clearly established.
Side-stepping the common employment doctrine, the House of Lords held that an employer was
deemed to owe a duty of care to his employees, which was personal to the employer and non-
delegable. Looking at the statutory schemes in place, Lord Thankerton highlighted the “fallacy” of
the argument that the employer, being under a duty to take due care in the provision of a reasonably
safe system of working, could then be absolved from that duty by the appointment of a competent
person to perform the duty.
50
The courts in this area were mindful of the rise in industrial
43
See the discussion of “social propositions” in M. Eisenberg, The Nature of the Common Law (1988) and in P. Sales,
“The Common Law: Context and Method” (2019) 135 LQR 47, 53-55.
44
[2001] 2 AC 127.
45
Ibid., see in particular: 200 (Lord Nicholls); 207–208 (Lord Steyn); 223–224 (Lord Cooke); 234 (Lord Hope).
46
See P. Mitchell, A History of Tort 1900-1950 (2014 CUP) chapter 8.
47
[1898] 2 QB 402, 406-7.
48
Ibid., 418.
49
[1938] AC 57.
50
Ibid., 64-65.
8
production methods and sought to ensure, through a re-framing of the common law duties of care
owed by employers, that employers paid compensation where those methods caused injury to their
employees. The fact that the duty was non-delegable, albeit the employer might have to appoint
an agent to carry it out, meant that the employer could not say the duty was discharged by its
appointment of a qualified person. The employer had to take the risk of that person negligently
making an error.
Although the legal relationship between employee and employer has become settled law, it should
be recalled that it was a highly political issue in the 19
th
and early 20
th
centuries. By referring to
statute, the courts had access to a legitimising source of public policy with a democratic warrant
authorised through the political process.
Similarly, the courts had to respond to the increasing use of motor vehicles in the 20
th
century.
51
In Croston v Vaughan
52
in 1938 the courts were faced with the question of the extent to which the
obligations under a statutory instrument informed the duty of care at common law. The trial judge
held two drivers jointly liable for injuries caused to the claimant in a road accident. The negligence
of one of them consisted in stopping suddenly and failing to give a hand signal. This finding was
challenged on appeal because the driver had used his brake light, which regulations required him
to have, and the Highway Code’s section on hand signals stated that they should be given “where
mechanical indicators are not used”.
53
For the majority of the Court of Appeal, compliance with
the Code and the regulatory requirement was insufficient to rebut an allegation of failure to take
reasonable care. As Scott LJ put it, the Code and the regulations “still leave upon every driver a
common law duty of taking action outside the Code and the regulations in circumstances where it
becomes essential.
54
For Slesser LJ, however, the relationship between the common law and the
regulations was being made too sophisticated: a driver who complied with the statutory regulations
on rear brake lights had, by definition, given adequate warning to the car behind and so had not
been negligent.
55
On Slesser LJ’s view, the negligence standard was given by the regulation. On the
view of the majority, the common law imposed its own autonomous standard. The difference in
approach highlights a basic choice which falls to be made in a range of contexts, including whether
a common law duty of care can be identified in the first place.
In general terms, the majority of statutes enacted in the area of the law of obligations presuppose
the existence of common law duties and can only work within the framework given by them.
56
For
example, the Law Reform (Contributory Negligence) Act 1945 makes no sense other than by
presupposing the common law of tort and legislating to modify it to some degree.
In some circumstances, however, the implication from the enactment of a statutory regime is that
Parliament has removed the ability for the courts to identify a duty of care by adopting their own
view of public policy. This is evident from the cases on the tort of breach of statutory duty, where
it is Parliament’s policy choice which is important. As Lord Scott explained in the Gorringe case: if
a statutory duty does not give rise to a private right to sue for breach, the duty cannot create a duty
of care that would not have been owed at common law if the statute were not there. If the policy
of the statute is not consistent with the creation of a statutory liability to pay compensation for
51
See Mitchell (n 46) chapter 7.
52
[1938] 1 KB 540.
53
Ministry of Transport, The Highway Code (London, HMSO, 1935) 16.
54
Croston (n 52), 564.
55
Ibid., 556.
56
See A. Burrows, “The Relationship between Common Law and Statute in the Law of Obligations” (2012) 128 LQR
232.
9
damage caused by a breach of the statutory duty, the same policy would, in my opinion, exclude
the use of the statutory duty in order to create a common law duty of care”.
57
However, it is for
the courts to infer what was Parliament’s choice regarding “the policy of the statute”, and in doing
that they may draw on their own understanding of what policy factors it is plausible to suppose
Parliament took into account.
58
5. References to statute to deny a duty of care at common law
Another category of case displays a similar reasoning pattern. The enactment of a statutory remedy
might serve as a signal to the courts that they should not develop the common law in the same
area. One could say that in these instances the statute operates as a sort of negative social
proposition, blocking the development of the common law. In Johnson v Unisys,
59
for example, the
essential question was whether the unfair dismissal legislation had frozen the development of the
common law on damages for breach of the contract of employment by the manner of the
dismissal. The House of Lords held that it should not develop the common law to allow wrongful
dismissal damages for mental distress or a psychiatric illness by way of a departure from the earlier
restrictive decision in Addis v Gramophone,
60
because to do so would undermine the special statutory
compensation scheme for unfair dismissal. Parliament had provided a remedy for such harm, but
at a much lower level than would be available if the common law categories of damage were
extended. The fact that Parliament had legislated for a remedy tended to diminish the pressure for
the common law to develop to reflect current social standards, and at the same time indicated that
it would be inappropriate for it to do so in a manner which would bypass the deliberate
compromise between competing interests enshrined in the statutory regime. If a positive choice
by Parliament is identified not to provide for a claim in damages, although it does not formally
prohibit the courts from developing the law to do just that, it operates as a guide as to the public
policy whether they should do so or not.
A different variation on this theme arises where it is clear that Parliament could have legislated in
an area, but has chosen not to. Since Parliament has the primary role in identifying public policy
and legislating to give effect to it, its abstention from legislation may indicate that, for public policy
reasons, the courts should also abstain from development of the law according to their own
judgment of public policy in the field. Courts are mindful of their own institutional limitations and
that legislative change of the law is primarily a matter for Parliament.
For example, in the Michael case the Supreme Court held that the police should have no liability in
the tort of negligence where they had failed to respond to a 999 call from a woman who was
murdered shortly afterwards by her former partner. As this involved a complex issue of social
policy, the Court considered that any development in this area was for Parliament.
61
In deciding
whether reform is best left to Parliament, courts may be mindful of whether or not Parliament has
demonstrated any willingness to legislate in this area, including whether they have done so in the
past, or to review whether legislation is required. If not, the inference may be that Parliament has
57
Gorringe (n 26), [71].
58
P. Sales, “In Defence of Legislative Intention” (2019) 48 Australian Bar Review 6, 18-19.
59
[2003] 1 AC 518.
60
[1909] AC 488.
61
Michael v Chief Constable of South Wales [2015] AC 1732, [130]. Cf Aitken v Scottish Ambulance Service [2011] CSOH 49
where it was said that a duty of care arose with respect to the manner in which the 999 call was responded to and an
ambulance despatched.
10
simply left the area free for development according to the usual processes of the common law and
courts may be more inclined to proceed to do that.
6. Public authorities
A significant chapter in the interface between statute and the law of tort concerns public authorities
which have statutory functions. A central tenet of the English legal tradition, most commonly
associated with the constitutional scholar Dicey, is the idea that public authorities and public
officials are subject to the ordinary law as administered in the ordinary courts. Indeed, for Dicey,
this equivalence principle was one of the three pillars of the rule of law.
62
English law begins from
the starting point that when exercising its public law functions a public authority is subject to the
same private law obligations as any other legal actor, and so can be liable in tort if in the course of
its performance of those functions it violates a private law right. The principle also applies in
negligence, as the Supreme Court reiterated in Robinson.
63
As made clear in the Gorringe and Michael cases, and most recently in Robinson, the equivalence
principle cuts both ways, in the sense that as a matter of private law analysis, public bodies and
officials are also, generally speaking, not subject to any additional liabilities by virtue of their status.
This means that “public authorities, like private individuals and bodies, are generally under no duty
of care to prevent the occurrence of harm”.
64
How far the analogy between public authorities and private persons can be taken is open to
question. As explained in Stovin v Wise: “Unlike an individual, a public authority is not an indifferent
onlooker. Parliament confers powers on public authorities for a purpose. An authority is entrusted
and charged with responsibilities, for the public good. The powers are intended to be exercised in
a suitable case.”
65
In other words, public authorities are expected and required to act in situations
where a private person is not. When considering whether to impose a duty of care on a public
authority, the court may find that its analysis has to be shaped to some extent by the special
position occupied by the defendant, since “the question whether there is such a common law duty
and if so its ambit, must be profoundly influenced by the statutory framework within which the
acts complained of were done”.
66
The statutory framework under which the defendant operates may make it plausible to argue that
it has a relationship of proximity with those whom the legislation is intended to benefit such as to
give rise to affirmative obligations towards such persons. Conversely, however, where a duty of
care would ordinarily be owed if a private person acted to assume a responsibility, it may be
excluded or restricted “where it would be inconsistent with the scheme of the legislation under
which the public authority is operating”.
67
62
A. V. Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution, (London: Macmillan, 8
th
edn, 1915) 114. An early
example of the operation of the equality principle is Mersey Docks and Harbour Board Trustees v Gibbs (1866) LR 1 HL
93.
63
Robinson (n 18), [32]-[33] (Lord Reed).
64
Ibid., [34] (Lord Reed). There are, of course, exceptions to this equivalence principle, such as the tort of misfeasance
in public office.
65
Stovin v Wise [1996] AC 923, 935.
66
X (Minors) (n 35), 739 (Lord Browne-Wilkinson).
67
Poole (n 34), [75] (Lord Reed).
11
In making that assessment it will be relevant that when imposing a duty or conferring a discretion
on the public authority, Parliament chose not to make it a duty sounding in damages.
68
Generally,
statutory discretions are not to be unduly fettered by the authority, which is required to preserve
its ability to adjust its behaviour in the light of changing circumstances so as to promote the
purposes of the statute and the common good. Breach of duty in public law does not sound in
damages. So even if a duty of care might appear to be capable of arising according to usual criteria
applicable in relation to private parties when a public authority takes action, it may be that to
impose such a duty would unduly limit the freedom of action of the authority to act in the public
interest. This might be contrary to the no-fettering principle, by creating a risk of liability in
damages if the authority decides to depart from an assurance given or course of action undertaken
in the exercise of its statutory functions. Public law has developed its own doctrine of legitimate
expectations to balance the no-fettering principle with standards of good government, especially
where there has been detrimental reliance by an individual,
69
and that balance could be distorted
if, in addition, the common law overlaid duties of care sounding in damages. It is to be expected
that this part of the interface between statute and the law of tort will require more examination in
future.
The most acute area of the interface arises where an individual claims that the public authority
owes them a duty of care in common law based on an assumption of responsibility to protect them
from a particular kind of harm. The harm might take the form of physical injury, damage to
property or pure economic loss. The assumption of responsibility relied on might be said to be
founded on what the authority has done in terms of positive action in the exercise of its statutory
functions. Assumption of responsibility as the foundation for a duty of care in tort in relation to
pure economic loss came to the fore in Hedley Byrne v Heller. The concept has had a vibrant life
since then, despite being subject to academic criticism.
70
However, the concept has deep historical roots and covers cases where a person chooses to enter
into particular forms of established relationship, such as relationships between doctor and
patient,
71
teacher and student,
72
and educational psychologist and child.
73
Generally, a public
authority which enters into such a relationship will become subject to a duty of care, even though
it did so in exercise of its statutory functions. It may be said that Parliament created the statutory
functions on the understanding that they would carry with them standard recognised duties of care
in tort.
But this inference as to Parliament’s intention does not carry across to areas where there is no
standard form of relationship already recognised at common law, and the role of the authority is
more purely “public” in nature. Schemes of public law which confer a high degree of discretion
are often seen as inconsistent with imposition of a common law duty of care. For example, in Davis
v Radcliffe
74
banking regulation powers in the Isle of Man were at issue. In denying that a duty of
care was owed to the claimant investors it was pointed out that the authority’s exercise of its
licensing powers “can well involve the exercise of judgment of a delicate nature affecting the whole
future of the relevant bank in the Isle of Man, and the impact of any consequent cessation of the
68
See X (Minors) (n 35)
69
See P. Sales and K. Steyn, “Legitimate Expectations in English Public Law: An Analysis” [2004] Public Law 564.
70
See P. Sales, “Pure Economic Loss and Assumption of Responsibility” (PNBA, Peter Taylor Memorial Address, 20
April 2023), available on the Supreme Court website.
71
See, e.g., D v East Berkshire Community NHS Trust [2003] 4 All ER 796.
72
See, e.g., X (Minors) (n 35).
73
See, e.g., Phelps v Hillingdon [2001] 2 AC 619.
74
[1990] 1 WLR 821.
12
bank’s business in the Isle of Man, not merely upon the customers and creditors of the bank, but
indeed upon the future of financial services in the island. In circumstances such as these,
competing considerations have to be carefully weighed and balanced in the public interest”.
75
The
imposition of a duty of care sounding in damages would cut across this scheme and distort the
decision-making flexibility the regulator was intended to enjoy.
But a discretion does not of itself rule out the possibility of a finding of an assumption of
responsibility. If, for example, in the exercise of its discretion, the public authority decides that it
should be doing something to benefit or protect a person, so it has itself decided to focus directly
on their protection in some way, it may be possible to say that the responsibility of the public
authority has been crystallised such that it creates a sufficient relationship of proximity to impose
a duty of care. This proximity is generally described as an assumption of responsibility by the
public authority. But since the language of assumption of responsibility is liable to be somewhat
misleading in this area, it may be better to say that, through the exercise of its statutory functions,
the public authority has itself brought about a focus of concern for and hence of responsibility for
the individual.
In public law family cases, the analogy between public and private defendants becomes very
attenuated. No private individual would intrude on another family’s affairs over a period of years,
as local authority social workers are frequently required to do. A private individual also lacks the
extraordinary legal powers enjoyed by local authorities, ultimately permitting removal of children
from their parents.
76
One difficult question the courts have sought to grapple with is why positive duties readily inhere
in some “general” relationships but not others.
77
In the final analysis, it is perhaps public policy
considerations that explain the categories and dividing lines in determining whether assumption
of responsibility has been established. In X v Bedfordshire a number of reasons were given to support
the conclusion that it was not just and reasonable to superimpose a common law duty of care on
the local authority in relation to the performance of its statutory duties to protect children. One
factor which weighed heavily with the court was that the existence of a common law duty of care
in relation to the statutory functions of the authority in question might have an adverse effect on
the way in which it discharged those functions. The local authority might adopt an unduly
defensive approach to its duties in relation to children at risk.
78
This reasoning soon came to be questioned. In Barrett v Enfield BC,
79
X v Bedfordshire was
distinguished on the grounds that in Barrett the authority had already taken the decision to take the
child from his home, and the statutory powers exercised by the local authority once he was in care
did not necessarily involve the exercise of the kind of discretion that was involved in taking the
child from his family into care in the first place. Furthermore, following the HRA, the Court of
Appeal held in D v East Berkshire NHS Trust that so far as the position of a child is concerned, the
decision in Bedfordshire cannot survive;
80
in light of the Strasbourg jurisprudence,
81
breaches of
Article 8 in child abuse cases may give rise to claims in negligence.
75
Ibid., 827.
76
J. Morgan, “A riddle wrapped in an enigma: assumption of responsibility, again” [2022] CLJ 449, 451.
77
See Michael (n 61), [179] (Lord Kerr); see also Robinson (n [18]), [115] (Lord Hughes).
78
X (Minors) (n 35), 681.
79
[2001] 2 AC 550.
80
Berkshire (n 71), [83].
81
Z v UK [2001] 2 FCR 246; TP v UK [2001] 2 FCR 289; P, C and S v UK [2002] 3 FCR 1.
13
But public policy still looms large in denying many duties at common law. The Capital and Counties
case
82
suggests, for example, that because fire brigades act for the benefit of the public
generally they do not assume responsibility to particular property-owners, especially as the public
interest and individuals’ interests could conflict (for example, property sacrificed to form a fire-
break). The “conflicting duties” argument is a particular powerful instance of the wider policy
concern that liability could incentivise undesirable behaviour.
83
As Lord Keith put it, “the cure may
be worse than the disease”.
84
More recently, the courts have sought to re-frame the discussion as one involving a distinction
between acts and omissions of public authorities. Defendants are not usually liable for failing to
assist, protect or otherwise make claimants better off. This usually entails that public authorities
will not be liable in negligence. Lord Reed in Robinson explained that many of the leading cases
denying public authority liability should now be recognised as applications of the nonfeasance
principle. Policy consideration in such cases is unnecessary. This approach was followed in the
Tindall case, in which the concept of “ineffectual interventions”
85
was placed within the omissions
category. They do not make the claimant’s situation worse, but merely fail to improve it. It was
“far too wideto suggest that whenever a public authority has power to prevent harm, a duty arises
to do so.
86
This reasoning is in keeping with the Stovin and Gorringe line of authorities. But the non-
feasance / misfeasance dividing line may be problematic in the case of a public authority subject
to public law duties to act. As Lord Hughes explained in Robinson: “The law readily finds [an
assumption of responsibility to act] in many common situations, such as employment, teaching,
healthcare and the care of children, and imposes liability for omitting to protect others. It could
equally readily do so in the case of police officers with a general public duty to protect the peace,
but it does not.”
87
In Poole Borough Council case, the Supreme Court reiterated the point it had made in Robinson that
the Caparo approach, which allows for the adjustment of the scope of a duty of care on grounds
of policy (under the “fair, just and reasonable” rubric), has no application in established categories
of case. It acknowledged that there may be circumstances, not present on the facts of that case,
where the local authority may assume a responsibility towards a particular child but did not give
details. But what is now clear is that a public authority does not assume responsibility for the
claimants’ safety merely by virtue of “investigating and monitoring the claimants’ position”, while
the mother’s “anxiety” to be rehoused did not “amount to reliance”.
88
Even if sufficient proximity
can be established on the facts of a particular case where there has been a positive act (rather than
a mere omission), it remains necessary to examine whether, in such a novel case, there are policy
reasons for not imposing a duty of care.
7. Interface of tort and statute beyond the duty of care
82
Capital and Counties plc v Hampshire CC [1997] QB 1004, 1036.
83
See H. Wilberg, “Defensive practice or conflict of duties? Policy concerns in public authority negligence claims
(2010) 126 LQR 420.
84
Rowling v Takaro Properties Ltd [1988] AC 473, 502. Similarly, the European Court of Human Rights seems to have
accepted the “defensive policing” argument: see Osman v United Kingdom [1998] ECHR 101.
85
Tindall v Chief Constable of Thames Valley [2022] EWCA Civ 25, [64].
86
Ibid., [71] (Stuart-Smith LJ).
87
Robinson (n 18), [115] (per Lord Hughes).
88
Poole (n 34), [81] (Lord Reed).
14
One final point to mention is that there are, of course, other areas of interface between statute and
tort. A classic example is false imprisonment which, as a form of trespass to the person, is a strict
liability tort. There is an interface between statute and tort in this area, because statute may give an
authority to detain someone and where it does, the detainer has a defence to the tort. However,
strict compliance with the statutory conditions is required in order to create the authority to detain.
Failing that, the defence does not arise. The Lumba case,
89
in which there were public law failures
by the Secretary of State in deciding to detain the claimants, makes this clear. This was so even
though it was accepted that it would have been inevitable that the claimants would have been
detained if the correct procedures had been followed. However, this was held to be relevant to the
quantum of damages.
90
Conclusion
It can be observed that the imposition or denial of the duty of care in the common law of tort has
been guided, to a significant degree, by judicial consideration of public policy in both the private
and public law contexts. Statutes play an important role in this regard. In the duty of care context,
judges have looked to statute as a helpful guide regarding public policy. Emphasis is given to
maintaining a harmonious and principled co-existence between statute and tort law. An
appreciation of the complex and nuanced interface between them serves to enrich the law of tort
and shows the importance for the judiciary of aiming to achieve coherence across the whole of the
law.
89
R (Lumba) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2012] 1 AC 245.
90
Ibid., [70] (Lord Dyson).